The Secularity of the Valentior Pars in the Philosophy of Marsilius of Padua
Abstract
Marsilius attributes the legislative authority to “the whole corporation of citizens or its weightier part” (universitas civium aut valentior pars). The ambiguity and vagueness of the expression “valentior pars” has caused different readings of Marsilius’s thought, in a more democratic (quantitate personarum) or more aristocratic (qualitate in communitate) sense. The analyse of this concept leads to the conclusion that the valentior pars, whichever configuration it has, and despite the theoretic difficulties, is the way to state that in any civitas the legislative authority must be absolutely lay. The paper explains that such an anticlerical meaning of the expression "weightier part" is the most congruent political application of it, because this part doesn’t represent particular interests, but the common interest; however, this one can't be represented by the priesthood, as a part of civil community. Therefore, if priests claim to make laws and have civil jurisdiction, they will obstruct the rightful political action, divide the community and bring the war.Downloads
References
Battaglia, F. (1924). Marsilio e il ‘Defensor pacis’. Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia del diritto, 4, 398-416.
Battaglia, F. (1929). Sul ‘Defensor packs’ di Marsilio da Padova. Nuovi studi di diritto economia e politica, 2, 128-146.
Bertelloni, F. (1984/85). ‘Constitutum Constantini’ y ‘Romgedanke’, La donación constantiniana en el pensamiento de tres defensores del derecho imperial de Roma: Dante, Marsilio de Padua y Guillermo de Ockham (2da parte). Patristica et Mediaevalia, 4/5, 67-99.
Bertelloni, F. (2002). Marsilio de Padua y la filosofía político medieval. En Bertelloni, F. & Burlando, C. (eds.). La Filosofía Medieval, Enciclopedia Iberoamericana de Filosofía, vol. XXIV. Madrid: Trotta-CSIS, 237-262.
Black, A. (1996). El pensamiento político en Europa (1250-1450). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bonnardi, A. (ed.). Rerum Italicarum Scriptores, vol. VIII, I. Città di Castello: S. Lapi.
Canning, J. P. (1988). Law, Sovereignty and Corporation Theory 1300-1450. In Burns, J. H. (ed.). The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c. 350-c.1450. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 454-476.
Capograssi, G. (1930). Intorno a Marsilio da Padova. Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia del diritto, 10, 578-590.
Carr, D. (1979). The Prince and the City: Ideology and Reality in the Thought of Marsilius of Padua. Medioevo (Rivista di storia della Filosofia medieval), 5, 279-291.
Castello Dubra, J. A. (2001). Marsilio de Padua y la teoría de la soberanía popular, Patristica et Mediaevalia, 22, 76-89.
Condren, C. (1980). Democracy and the ‘Defensor pacis’: on the English Language Tradition of Marsilian Interpretation. Il Pensiero Politico, 13(3), 301-306.
De Lagarde, G. (1970). La naissance de l’esprit laïque au déclin du Moyen Âge, Marsile de Padoue, III, Le Defensor Pacis. Louvain/Paris: Nauwelaerts.
Dolcini, C. (1995). Introduzione a Marsilio da Padova. Roma/Bari: Laterza.
García Cue, J. R. (1985). Teoría de la ley y de la soberanía popular en el ‘Defensor pacis’ de Marsilio de Padua. Revista de Estudios Políticos (Nueva Época), 43, 107-148.
Gewirth, A. (1951). Marsilius of Padua, The Defender of Peace, vol. I: Marsilius of Padua and the Medieval Political Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.
Gewirrt, A. (1979). Republicanism and Absolutism in the Thought of Marsilius of Padua. Medioevo (Rivista di storia della Filosofia medieval), 5, 23-48.
Hyde, J. K. (1985). Padova nell’ età di Dante. Trieste: Edizione Lint.
Lewis, E. (1954). Medieval Political Ideas, I. London: Routledge.
Lewis, E. (1963). The ‘positivism’ of Marsiglio of Padua. Speculum, 38(4), 541-582.
Marangon, P. (1977). Marsilio tra Preumanesimo e cultura delle arti, Ricerca sulle fonti padovane del primo discorso del ‘Defensor pacis’. Medioevo (Rivista di storia della filosofia medievale), 3, 89-119.
Mc Ilwain, C. H. (1959). Il pensiero politico occidentale dai Greci al tardo Medioevo. Venezia: N. Pozza.
Merlo, M. (2003). Marsilio da Padova, Il pensiero della politica come grammatica del mutamento. Milano: Franco Angeli.
Monahan, A. P. (1987). Consent, Coercion and Limit: The Medieval Origins of Parlamentary Democracy. Kingston/Montreal: McGill/ Queens University Press.
Moulin, L. (1980). Une source méconnue de la philosophie politique marsilienne: l’organisation constitutionnelle des ordres religieux. Medioevo, 6, 337-345.
Nederman, C. (1991). Knowledge, Consent, and the Critique of the Political Representation in Marsiglio of Padua’s ‘Defensor pacis’. Political Studies, 39, 19-35.
Nederman, C. (1993). Writings on the Empire, Defensor Minor and De Translatione Imperii. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nederman, C. (1995). Community and Consent, The Secular Political Theory of Marsiglio of Padua’s ‘Defensor pacis’. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.
Passerin d’Entreves, A. (1939). The Medieval Contributions to Political Thought: Thomas Aquinas, Marsilius of Padua, Richard Hooker. Oxford: Humanities Press.
Piaia, G. (2003). Marsilio da Padova, Niccolò de Rossi e la propaganda pro e contra Giovanni XXII. In Theoretische Reflexion und soziale Erfahrung, Symposion zum Verhältnis von sozialer Erfahrung und politischer Theorie im späten Mittelalter im lnternationalen Wissenschaftsforum der Universität Heidelberg, en honor del Prof. Jürgen Miethke.
Pincin, C. (1967). Marsilio. Torino: Giappichelli.
Quaglioni, D. (1983). Politica e diritto nel trecento italiano, Pensiero Politico. Roma: Leo S. Olschki.
Quillet, J. (1970). La philosophie politique de Marsile de Padoue. Paris: Vrin.
Quillet, J. (1971). ‘Universitas populi’ et représentation au XIVe. siècle. Miscellanea Mediaevalia, VIII: Der Begriff der Representativo im Mittelalter. Berlin.
Quillet, J. (1988). Community, Counsel and Representation. In Burns, J. H. (ed.). The Cambridge History of Medieval Political Thought, c. 350-c.1450. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 520-572.
Scholz, R. (1907). Marsilius von Padua und die Idee der Demokratie. Zeitschrift für Politik, 1, 61-94.
Segal, H. (1959). Der Defensor Pacis des Marsilius von Padua, Grundfragen und Interpretation. Wiesbaden: F. Steiner.
Sternberger, D. (1981). Die Stadt und das Reich in der Verfassungslehre des Marsilius von Padua. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.
Sternberger, D. (1985). Die Stadt als Urbild: sieben politische Beiträge. Frankfurt am Main/Berlin: Suhrkamp.
Tursi, A. (1997). ‘Communitas aut valencior eius pars’. Un giro marsiliano en Nicolás de Oresme y la composición del ‘De monte’. Patristica et Mediaevalia, 18, 59-80.
Wilks, M. (1972). Corporation and Representation in the ‘Defensor pacis’. Studio Gratiana, 15, 279-287.
1. The authors who publish in this magazine accept the following conditions:
-
They retain the copyright and grant to the magazine the right of the first publication, with the work registered under the Attribution-ShareAlike 4.0 International License that allows third parties to use what is published as long as they mention the authorship of the work and the first publication in this magazine.
-
They can make other independent and additional contractual agreements for the non-exclusive distribution of the version of the article published in this magazine (eg. include it in an institutional repository or publish it in a book) provided that they clearly indicate that the work was first published in this journal.
-
They are allowed and recommended to publish their work on the Internet (for example on institutional or personal pages).
2. AutoArchive Conditions. Authors are allowed and encouraged to distribute post-print electronic versions of their manuscripts because it promotes their circulation, a possible increase of quotation and a major reach among the Academic community. Color RoMEO: blue.